∞Intro to the Theory of Sets Unit 8 – Cardinal Numbers and Arithmetic
Cardinal numbers represent set sizes, from finite to infinite. They're crucial for comparing and manipulating sets in mathematics. Understanding cardinals helps us grasp the concept of infinity and its various "sizes."
Cardinal arithmetic extends basic operations to infinite sets. It reveals surprising properties, like how adding or multiplying an infinite cardinal by itself doesn't change its value. This field connects set theory to other math branches and computer science.
Cardinal numbers represent the size or cardinality of a set, indicating how many elements are in the set
Finite cardinal numbers correspond to the natural numbers (0, 1, 2, 3, ...) and represent the number of elements in a finite set
Infinite cardinal numbers, such as ℵ0 (aleph-null), represent the cardinality of infinite sets (the set of natural numbers)
Two sets have the same cardinality if there exists a bijection (one-to-one correspondence) between them
The cardinality of a set A is denoted as ∣A∣
The empty set, denoted as ∅, has a cardinality of 0
Cardinal numbers are used to compare the sizes of sets and perform arithmetic operations on them
Properties of Cardinal Numbers
Cardinal numbers are well-ordered, meaning that for any two cardinal numbers, one is always less than or equal to the other
The smallest infinite cardinal number is ℵ0, which represents the cardinality of the set of natural numbers
For any cardinal number κ, there exists a next larger cardinal number, denoted as κ+
For example, the next larger cardinal after ℵ0 is ℵ1
The continuum hypothesis states that there is no cardinal number between ℵ0 and 2ℵ0 (the cardinality of the real numbers)
The continuum hypothesis is independent of the standard axioms of set theory (ZFC)
The generalized continuum hypothesis states that for any infinite cardinal κ, there is no cardinal between κ and 2κ
The axiom of choice implies that every set can be well-ordered, and thus, every set has a cardinal number
Basic Arithmetic with Cardinals
Addition of cardinal numbers: For two sets A and B, ∣A∣+∣B∣=∣A∪B∣ if A and B are disjoint
If A and B are not disjoint, ∣A∣+∣B∣=∣A∪B∣+∣A∩B∣
Multiplication of cardinal numbers: For two sets A and B, ∣A∣⋅∣B∣=∣A×B∣, where A×B is the Cartesian product of A and B
Exponentiation of cardinal numbers: For two sets A and B, ∣A∣∣B∣=∣BA∣, where BA is the set of all functions from A to B
For infinite cardinal numbers, addition and multiplication are idempotent, meaning κ+κ=κ and κ⋅κ=κ for any infinite cardinal κ
The distributive law holds for cardinal arithmetic: κ⋅(λ+μ)=κ⋅λ+κ⋅μ
Comparing Cardinal Numbers
Two sets A and B have the same cardinality (∣A∣=∣B∣) if there exists a bijection between them
A set A has a smaller cardinality than a set B (∣A∣<∣B∣) if there exists an injection from A to B, but no bijection between them
Cantor's theorem states that for any set A, the power set of A (P(A)) has a strictly larger cardinality than A
This implies that there is no "largest" cardinal number
The Cantor-Bernstein-Schroeder theorem states that if there exist injections from A to B and from B to A, then ∣A∣=∣B∣
The cardinality of the natural numbers (ℵ0) is less than the cardinality of the real numbers (2ℵ0)
This is demonstrated by Cantor's diagonalization argument
Infinite Cardinals and Aleph Numbers
Aleph numbers (ℵ0,ℵ1,ℵ2,... are used to represent the cardinalities of infinite sets
ℵ0 represents the cardinality of the set of natural numbers, which is the smallest infinite cardinal
The next larger cardinal after ℵ0 is ℵ1, followed by ℵ2, and so on
The continuum hypothesis states that 2ℵ0=ℵ1, but this is independent of the standard axioms of set theory (ZFC)
The generalized continuum hypothesis states that for any infinite cardinal κ, 2κ=κ+, where κ+ is the next larger cardinal after κ
The cofinality of an infinite cardinal κ is the smallest cardinal λ such that κ can be expressed as the union of λ smaller sets
Regular cardinals are those whose cofinality is equal to themselves, while singular cardinals have a smaller cofinality
Cardinal Arithmetic in Set Theory
Cardinal arithmetic is an essential part of set theory, as it allows for the comparison and manipulation of the sizes of sets
The axiom of choice is often used in proofs involving cardinal arithmetic, as it ensures that every set can be well-ordered
The continuum hypothesis and its generalization are important topics in cardinal arithmetic, although they are independent of ZFC
König's theorem states that if κ is an infinite cardinal and λ is a cardinal with λ<cf(κ), then λ<κ<κ
Here, λ<κ represents the cardinality of the set of all functions from a set of cardinality <κ to a set of cardinality λ
The singular cardinal hypothesis (SCH) is a generalization of König's theorem, stating that for any singular cardinal κ, κcf(κ)=κ+
Large cardinal axioms, such as the existence of inaccessible, measurable, or supercompact cardinals, have significant implications for cardinal arithmetic and the structure of the universe of sets
Applications and Examples
Cardinal numbers are used in various branches of mathematics, including topology, algebra, and analysis
In topology, the cardinality of a topological space can be used to classify spaces and study their properties
For example, separable spaces are those with a countable dense subset (cardinality ≤ℵ0)
In algebra, cardinal numbers are used to study the sizes of algebraic structures, such as groups, rings, and fields
The cardinality of a group can determine its properties and behavior
In analysis, cardinal numbers are used to study the sizes of function spaces and the properties of real and complex numbers
The cardinality of the continuum (2ℵ0) is a fundamental concept in real analysis
In computer science, cardinal numbers are used to analyze the complexity of algorithms and data structures
The cardinality of input sets can affect the running time and space requirements of algorithms
Common Pitfalls and Misconceptions
It is important to distinguish between cardinal numbers and ordinal numbers, which represent the order type of well-ordered sets
The arithmetic of infinite cardinal numbers does not always behave like the arithmetic of finite numbers
For example, ℵ0+1=ℵ0 and ℵ0⋅2=ℵ0
The continuum hypothesis is a statement about the possible cardinalities between ℵ0 and 2ℵ0, not a proven fact
Not all infinite sets have the same cardinality, as demonstrated by Cantor's theorem and the existence of uncountable sets (real numbers)
The axiom of choice is required for certain proofs in cardinal arithmetic, but it is independent of the other axioms of ZFC
Some results, such as the well-ordering theorem, depend on the axiom of choice
Cardinal exponentiation is not always commutative, especially for infinite cardinals